Dialego, Philosophy,
and Class Struggle
In 1976, in
the year of the Soweto uprising, ten years after the “Tricontinental”, four
articles were published in the African Communist, written by John Hoffman under the
pen-name “Dialego”. The first two are linked below, as our main texts for
today.
Hoffman
still teaches philosophy at Leicester University in England. He is no longer
trying to be a revolutionary, but is an overt liberal these days. His
liberalism of today is foreshadowed in these works of three and a half decades
ago. His liberalism, now, is a child of his “Dialectical Materialism”, then.
“Dialectical Materialism” is not revolutionary, but it is liberal. We will
develop this argument in due course.
Hoffman’s
four articles were subsequently republished, more than once, as a set, in a
booklet. (Click here for Part 3 and Part 4 if required). The articles were
popular with MK and are still famous. They certainly raised the banner of
theory high. But they contained major deficiencies, of which the principal one
is “Dialectical Materialism” itself.
We are
going to return to the history of “Dialectical Materialism” in the next part of
this series. Then we will look again, in the following two parts, at the much
more fruitful Subject-Object relation, where priority is given to the free
human Subject, before finishing in the tenth and last part of the series with
new theoretical developments and ways forward for philosophy.
Hoffman (in
his Part 2) writes of “Materialism vs. Idealism: the Basic Question of
Philosophy”. But the Fundamental Question of Philosophy is the relation of the
Subject to the Object, and not “Materialism vs. Idealism”. Glaring errors arise
if and when these two different formulations are conflated into one.
For
example, going back to Hoffman’s Part 1 under “Philosophy and Our
‘Experience’”, Hoffman writes about “stress[ing] the materialist component of
our philosophy at the expense of the dialectical”. This is a muddle. What he is
describing is what he himself is doing: idealising the objective factors of a
situation, while all but eliminating the human Subject.
An original
causation is demanded, which then has to be given a higher status than all
else. Out goes God. In come the atoms and the molecules.
In this way
of thinking (dialectical materialism) the atoms and the molecules, the
inanimate a priori material, take
precedence over life. This is “ashes to ashes, dust to dust” dressed up as
revolutionary theory. But this cannot be.
Revolution
is a quality of life, not ashes.
The
dialectic that is political is the one between subjective humans and the
objective universe (which is indeed material). In this political dialectic, the
human Subject is the “point”.
As Marx
wrote in the 11th Thesis on Feuerbach: “Philosophers have hitherto
only interpreted the world in various ways; the point is to change it.” Who’s point is that? It is our point. It is
the human beings’ point. We are humanists. We are on the side of the humans,
and of their humanity, which we ourselves have created and continue to create
out of the world’s mud, through labour.
A purely
material event is like a tree falling in the forest, unseen and unheard by
anyone. It is a real event, but it is not a political event.
Similarly,
a switch from an imaginary world of superstition to one that fetishises inert
material is no gain at all. These are merely two different forms of idealism.
In both
these latter cases, powers are held up that are higher than people, whether the
powers are invisible or visible. But in politics, the power that matters is
people-power. For sure, that means people-power in a real, material world. But
it does not mean a “balancing act” between the human and the inhuman.
There is no
dialectic of the ideal versus the material. These two categories are not
interdependent, but constitute alternatives: either/or.
But there is
certainly a dialectic of the Subject and the Object, because these two
categories define each other. They are inseparable in their opposition to one
another. But people still come first. People have priority. The Subject, who
labours, is what it is all about, and not the material Object.
Hoffman’s
(then) devotion to “materialism” led him to write that “[man] developed out of the world of nature through a long process of
evolution and his ideas are the product of the mental activity of his brain,
itself a highly developed and complex form of matter.”
How does a
“complex form of matter” become human? Actually, it is not even necessary to
ask. It is only Hoffman’s kind of “materialism” that leads to such miserable,
reductionist questions: questions that run away from humanity.
The atoms
and molecules may be taken as “given”, whether by God or by chance. But
humanity is special, while matter is only matter. Humanity is historical, while
matter is infinite. Humanity is revolutionary work-in-progress. Humanity is
what humans make. Making humanity is what humans do. It is the free-willing
human Subject that is at the centre of our consciousness, our concerns, our
morality, and our politics.
- The above is to introduce the original reading-texts: Dialego, Part 1, Necessity of Theory, 1976, John Hoffman and Dialego, Part 2, Theory of Action, 1976, John Hoffman.
- To download any of the CU courses in PDF files please click here.
No comments:
Post a Comment